International Conference

on

Linguistic Evidence

  Original Call
  Invited Speakers
  Program
  Posters
  Instructions for Authors
  Conference Home
  SFB Home page

Invited Talk

Carson Schütze (UCLA)

Garbage In, Garbage Out: Thinking about what we're asking subjects to do

In this talk I want to focus on several behavioural tasks commonly used in (psycho)linguistic research and encourage a (re)consideration of the following issues:
1) Are we asking our subjects to do something reasonable, i.e. something we believe that (sometimes) linguistically naive speakers understand and can carry out?
2) Do we have sufficient reason to believe that they are doing what we think they're doing in generating responses to our tasks?
3) Might there be better ways to get at the constructs we are interested in, i.e. better tasks or wordings of tasks that would lead subjects to respond in a way more directly reflective of the cognitive systems we intend to study?

I suggest that the answers to these questions are, respectively: No in some cases; not necessarily, in some cases; and I think so, and I invite the participants to ask themselves and each other this question more often. Two examples follow.

One area where it is notoriously difficult to collect consistent data involves relative scope of two or more operators (quantifiers, modals, negation, etc.) within a sentence. Grammaticality judgments of particular scope readings seem difficult even for linguists, and often not worth trying on naive subjects, even if posed in the form "Can this sentence mean that there are at least two cars that Mary didn't wash?" etc. I submit that this is the wrong task to use for this purpose, and that we should take a methodological page from the book of child language acquisition. Specifically, we should apply the Truth Value Judgment Task (Crain & McDaniel 1985) to such problems: the linguist/experimenter describes a real-world scenario (perhaps with a diagram, to reduce short-term memory load) and asks the subject whether the target sentence is true in that situation. This moves the task (almost?) out of the realm of the metalinguistic and puts it in a maximally natural context; more importantly, it reduces the task demands--the meaning of just one multi-quantifier sentence needs to be computed. By contrast, the traditional scenario described above requires processing two sentences: the target ("Mary didn't wash two cars") and the (supposedly) unambiguous paraphrase, and comparing the resulting meanings, which is complicated by the fact that the sentences overlap almost completely in lexical content and are hence hard to keep apart.

A second example arises in the domain of morphology: the Wug test (Gleason 1958), where subjects are induced to generated forms from an inflectional paradigm for a nonce root. On all sides of the "Dual Mechanism" debates, the results are taken to reflect the subject's current representation of knowledge of the inflectional system (whether it be rules, associations, or both), but this ignores another crucial module of the mind. What are we really asking subjects to do when we ask them to imagine the existence of a nonce verb like 'spling'? There are two importantly different tasks they could implicitly undertake. One is what we can call the dictionary scenario: We are saying "I bet you didn't know this, but if you look in the dictionary you'll find English has an obscure verb "spling"; now, tell me what you think its past tense is." The other is what we can call the neologism scenario: We are saying "I've just decided to make up a new word to describe this really cool way of bouncing a paper clip that I discovered. Now, how do you think I should say it in the past tense?" (The latter is more or less explicitly how the task is presented to children.)

Under the dictionary scenario, it would be reasonable for the subject to make a judgment about the shape of the (static) lexicon of English: for a speaker of 50 years ago who had 'spling' in their vocabulary along with all the words the subject already knows, how would that verb most likely have been inflected? Under the neologism scenario, it would be reasonable for the subject to do a couple of things: 1) invoke knowledge of how novel or "weird" words inflect (as has been argued for the alleged default German noun plural -s); or 2) treat the word as if they were acquiring it in the normal course of everyday events, i.e. run it through the Language Acquisition Device (LAD), the aforementioned neglected player in this mental game. Now, given what we know about the history of irregular inflection, most likely our LAD does not simply dump new roots into the default class until it encounters direct evidence for an irregularity; rather, it probably makes guesses as to inflectional patterning based on the shape of the root (in languages that have such patterns). This would be the same sort of "guess" that the LAD of speakers 50 years ago would have made during childhood, so it might lead to responses similar to the dictionary scenario. Thus, two points should be clear: there is a disturbing amount of leeway in how subjects could respond to a Wug task, and it is not immediately obvious which kind of response we want them to make, indeed this may differ with one's theoretical perspective. (E.g., the Albright & Hayes learner seeks to model Wug test behavior with a system of rules that play no role in producing forms of words that a speaker already knows.)


Stephan Kepser
Last modified: Fri Feb 13 16:18:25 MET